at the National Endowment for the Arts
An
interdisciplinary
education project partially funded by the American Bar Association,
Commission
on College and University Legal Studies through the ABA Fund for
Justice
and Education
THE FIRST AMENDMENT Site Table of Contents |
This section addresses four sets of issues concerning free speech under the first amendment:
A. Our freedom of speech, protected by the First Amendment in the Bill of Rights, is one of our most basic constitutional rights. Yet the precise nature of what is protected by the First Amendment is often misunderstood.
B. The word speech in the First Amendment has been extended to a generous sense of "expression" -- verbal, non-verbal, visual, symbolic. The artistic work supported by the NEA includes a variety of types of expression enjoying this broad protection.
C. Various exceptions to free speech have been recognized in American law, including obscenity, defamation, breach of the peace, incitement to crime, "fighting words," and sedition.
D. The work of major philosophers who have considered freedom of expression (e.g., J.S. Mill and Joel Feinberg) is helpful in explaining the rationale for these exceptions.
|
![]() |
This image is the joint resolution of Congress in 1789 proposing amendments to the Constitution, now known as the Bill of Rights. It is on permanent display in the Rotunda of the National Archives. You can display a high-resolution image of the Bill of Rights (87 K JPEG).
The First Amendment to the United States Constitution says that Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of "speech." Close attention to these few important words reveals several issues demanding interpretation and clarification.
Note that the document uses the word "speech," although a long succession of court decisions has expanded this concept far beyond ordinary verbal communication. Protected expression now includes such non-verbal expression as wearing a symbol on one's clothing, dance movements, and a silent candlelight vigil.
Consider
how the concept of "speech" has been broadened by the courts. What is
"speech"
for these constitutional purposes? Must it constitute communication?
expression?
expression of what? Must it use a language of some verbal or non-verbal
sort to receive this protection? What do we mean by a language? Are
there
forms of expression which we would not want protected?
Also note that the language is a prohibition on Congressional action. The First Amendment applies only when Congress passes a law abridging speech. Suppressions of speech are not violations of the First Amendment unless the State does the suppressing. The State could be either the Federal government or (now) a State government. Many mistakenly thank that any suppression of speech, including suppression by private citizens, violates the First Amendment. Such a private action might be objectionable for ethical or social reasons, but it does not present a constitutional issue.
If a record company decides to drop a certain
rap group from its roster
of recording artists, has the First Amendment been violated? If a U.S.
Senator makes a speech in which he says he personally wishes that
Hollywood
would stop making X-rated moves, has the First Amendment been violated?
If the wife of a Vice-President of the United States urges that
recording
companies adopt a voluntary rating system to warn parents about
offensive
content, has the First Amendment been violated?
Why
it is that one might still object to these private suppressions of
speech,
even when the government is not involved. Are these ethical concerns?
If
so, what ethical principles are at stake? Should all citizens be urged
on moral grounds to allow freedom of expression by all of their fellow
citizens and not attempt to suppress that speech as private citizens?
Would
the First Amendment be improved if it prohibited abridgement of speech
by anyone, not just Congress? Should every citizen have a right
to say anything at all with no suppression by fellow citizens? Are
there
times when private citizens not only could but should suppress the
speech
of their fellow citizens?
Controversies about speech protected by the First Amendment seem to arise because the speech at issue is unpopular or controversial or highly offensive for various reasons. Yet a hallmark of the Bill of Rights is protection of minority views. If the First Amendment only protected popular speech, supported by the majority of citizens, then the constitutional protection would not be needed. Instead we could simply have a referendum with the majority deciding which speech should be allowed. In a sense, of course, Congressional representation constitutes a majority referendum. If the majority of citizens is presumed to speak through Congress, and if a majority of Congress votes to ban certain speech, then the First Amendment intervenes to prohibit that suppression by the majority.
Should
we protect minority views? Are there minority views we should protect,
while others should be suppressed? How should such a distinction be
made?
If a statement is offensive to someone, should it be suppressed? If it
harms someone, should it be suppressed? what do we mean by harm?
Speech includes much more than verbal oration and need not include any words. The expression of artists, including the use of symbolism, is protected under the First Amendment. The wearing of armbands with a peace symbol was protected during the Vietnam War as symbolic speech protected under the First Amendment. (Tinker v. Des Moines School District, 393 U.S. 503 [1969]) Yet the burning of a draft card was not considered protected speech but an illegal behavior violating the Selective Service rules (United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.S. 367 [1968]).
A continuing issue is the precise nature of artistic and symbolic speech that is protected versus behavior that is not. Justice David Souter recently listed some of the forms of artistic expression protected under the First Amendment which have been recognized by the U.S. Supreme Court: painting, music, poetry, motion pictures, dramatic works, radio and television entertainment, drawings, and engravings. (NEA v. Finley, No. 97-371, 1998)
How
should we make distinctions between artistic and symbolic speech that
is
protected and illegal behavior that is not? Should performance art that
includes many overt, physical behaviors be protected as symbolic
speech?
What might we mean by a symbol in the context of the First Amendment?
Is
that the same sense we might use when interpreting, for example, the
symbolism
in a work of art?
What does Tinker v. Des Moines School
District mean today, almost
30 years later? A new Web site, produced by the American Bar
Association,
Division of Public Education, includes discussions with the students
who
were the original plaintiffs in this case, along with extensive
information
about the case: http://www.abanet.org/publiced/lawday/tinker/home.html
C. Exceptions to Freedom of Expression
Many exceptions to the First Amendment protections have been recognized by the courts, although not without controversy. Courts sometimes justify these exceptions as speech which causes substantial harm to the public, or speech which the Founding Fathers could not have intended to protect, or traditions that have long been part of the common law tradition from England that was the basis of our American legal system.
Rather than merely reciting the list of established exceptions, it is important to understand the rationale for making exceptions to free speech protection under the Constitution. The value of free speech sometimes clashes with other important values in our culture.
How
should we weigh the relative importance of these competing social
values?
How do we balance free speech against racism, sexism, or anti-Semitism
which promotes values we despise as a country? against speech which
some
consider a symptom of the decay of society's traditional values?
against
speech which directly results in physical injury to another person?
Exceptions established by the courts to the First Amendment protections include the following:
(1) Defamation: Defamation consists of a publication of a statement of alleged fact which is false and which harms the reputation of another person.(1) Our right to freedom of expression is restricted when our expressions (whether a spoken slander or written libel) cause harm to the reputation of another person. The courts recognize that words can hurt us, for example, by harming our ability to earn a living (economic harm).
This exception to freedom of expression can be difficult to apply in practice. Defamation requires an allegation of a fact which is in fact false. In contrast, the expression of an opinion is not considered defamation.
Imagine
an artistic exhibit claiming that certain named persons, ordinary
citizens
were child molesters or had a secret Nazi past or earned extra income
as
prostitutes. If these are viewed strictly as factual claims which are
false,
they would seem to constitute defamation. But what if the artist said
she
was expressing a symbolic commentary or creating a metaphor about the
secret
lives of ordinary people, not making an allegation of fact? How should
we draw the line in an artistic work between a factual statement and a
symbolic or metaphorical opinion?
Some
years ago, on an eastern college campus, flyers were distributed with
the
names of male students randomly drawn from the student directory, with
the label that they were potential rapists. Assume, for the sake of
argument,
that this is guerrilla theater art. Were these flyers statements? Were
they false statements? Were the reputations of the male students
harmed?
Should these expressions be protected by the First Amendment if the
expressions
were made by artists? Should we allow such statements, even if they are
defamatory, if they are made by artists? How then should we decide who
counts as an artist for this exception to the prohibition on defamation?
In 1990, Donald E. Wildmon, Executive Director of the American Family Association, published a pamphlet which include excerpts from the work of artist David Wojnarowicz in an exhibit, "Tongues of Flame." The artist sued Wildmon and the AFA for (among other things) defamation. Although the court agreed that "By presenting what are, standing alone, essentially pornographic images as plaintiff's works of art, without noting that the images are merely details from larger composite works, the pamphlet is libelous per se." However, as Wojnarowicz was considered a "public figure," he also had to show that Wildmon acted with reckless disregard for the truth. The court held that this higher standard had not been met. (For the text of this court decision, see Wojnarowicz v. American Family Association, 745 F.Supp. 130 [S.D.N.Y. 1990]).
Do you agree with Wojnarowicz that presentation
of his work out of context
was defamatory? What considerations support the artist's claims? What
arguments
can be raised against the artist's claims?
(2) Causing panic: The classic example of speech which is not protected by the First Amendment, because it causes panic, is falsely shouting "fire" in a crowded theater. (2) This is narrowly limited to situations in which a reasonable person would know that it was very likely that his or her speech would really cause harm to others. We can imagine works of art which might cause real panic among the audience, perhaps a contemporary version of Orson Welles' War of the Worlds, which caused considerable panic when it first aired on the radio, and in turn was based on H.G. Wells The War of the Worlds.
Imagine
that a guerilla theater group staged a fake emergency which a
reasonable
person would expect would almost certainly cause real panic among the
audience.
This might be a theater production during which the director plans to
yell
"fire" and cause a stampede by the audience to the exit doors. Should
this
exercise of freedom of expression by artists be protected by the First
Amendment? Or could we argue that the panic resulted simply because
naive
audience members were unsophisticated about how to approach art and
that
freedom of expression should prevail? Perhaps (one might argue) they do
not know how to assume an "aesthetic attitude" or appropriately
"distance"
themselves from a work of art.
(3) Fighting words: In the famous case of Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, the U.S. Supreme Court held that the First Amendment does not protect "fighting words -- those which by their very utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace." (315 U.S. 568, 572 [1942]) This famous exception is much discussed in recent decades, but rarely the basis for a decision upholding an abridgement of free speech.
This exception warrants scrutiny. Note that the harm involved is physical harm caused by someone else who was provoked by the speaker whose speech is being suppressed. The fact that someone else flies into a rage and causes physical harm results in justifying suppression of speech by another person!
It
is worth considering why this exception has declined in acceptance. Are
we now more skeptical of claims that people cannot control their
actions?
Do we demand the exercise of more responsibility by persons regardless
of what inflammatory words they might hear? Are we more suspicious of
claims
of causal necessity in such situations? Note the irony that we are also
witnessing an increase in the so-called "abuse excuse" in which we seem
more likely to excuse someone's behavior because of something someone
else
did to them. Is this inconsistent with the decline in the fighting
words
exception?
(4) Incitement to crime: It is a crime to incite someone else to commit a crime, and such speech is not protected by the First Amendment.
If
a budding rap group proposes to perform a work which includes the
exhortation
to "kill whitie" or "kill the cops" or "rape the babe," could that be
incitement
to a crime? Such records have been sold by commercial organizations, of
course, yet there are no reported arrests of those artists or record
companies
for incitement to a crime. Should such rap lyrics be considered
incitement
to crime or is the causal relationship to any actual murders or rapes
too
tenuous?
A
novel criminal defense has arisen, claiming that such music somehow
compelled
the defendant to commit the crime. In Austin, Texas, Ronald Ray Howard,
charged with the capital murder of a state trooper, claimed in his
defense
that ". . . he learned to hate police officers from years of listening
to rap music with violent anti-police themes. . . . "(3)
Is this an acceptable defense? Why or why not? (The jury convicted him,
reaching a verdict in 35 minutes.)
The
recent attention to violence on television is largely a debate over
whether
such televised violence is a cause of actual violence, such
that
persons who exhibit violent shows should be held responsible. If
society
wants to discourage violence on television, is it because such depicted
violence is clearly a cause of actual violence? Are there other reasons
why society might still feel justified in restricting this depiction?
It
is easy to imagine highly unpalatable projects which arguably could be
considered an incitement to crime. What if a fundamentalist religious
extremist
group publishes a guidebook in this country on how to commit terrorism
in the United States, with detailed instructions on making bombs, maps
showing the homes and offices of government officials, and so forth.
Instructions
alone would not seem to constitute incitement, so assume that the book
will also include a statement from the religion's most revered leader
urging
that the guaranteed path to eternal bliss is following the instructions
in the book. Given the presumed audience, might this be incitement to
crime?
(5) Sedition: Although not without controversy, the U.S. Supreme Court has upheld statutes which prohibit the advocacy of unlawful conduct against the government or the violent overthrow of the government. As with prohibitions discussed earlier, the expressions in question are assessed according to the circumstances. Academic discussion of the theories of, say, Karl Marx presumably would not be prohibited under such a test, especially in this post-Soviet era. The theoretical consideration and even endorsement of these views could not remotely be considered to be reasonable expectations of the actual overthrow of the government. But it is possible that an artist might develop a project, perhaps guerrilla theater or an exhibit, that urged the destruction of the United States (the "Great Satan") by extremist religious groups. The likelihood of success by the latter group would seem as improbable as the likelihood of success by contemporary Marxists.
If
the discussion of Marx should not be prohibited as sedition, should we
be consistent and allow discussion by the religious extremist? Are
there
any grounds upon which we could distinguish these situations?
(6) Obscenity: In Miller v. California (413 U.S. 14 [1973]) the U.S. Supreme Court established a three-pronged test for obscenity prohibitions which would not violate the First Amendment:
(a) whether the average person, applying contemporary community standards, would find that the work, taken as a whole, appeals to the prurient interest; (b) whether the work depicts or describes, in a patently offensive way, sexual conduct specifically defined by the applicable state law; and (c) whether the work, taken as a whole, lacks serious literary, artistic, political or scientific value.Although much debated, this standard remains the law of the land, and elements of this language have been included in both the authorizing legislation for the National Endowment for the Arts (20 U.S.C. 951 et seq.) and the Communications Decency Act (4) prohibiting "obscenity" and "indecency" on the Internet. The Communications Decency Act was struck down as unconstitutional by the U.S. Supreme Court in June 1997. The NEA legislation was been struck down as unconstitutional by lower courts but was upheld by the U.S. Supreme Court in 1998. (NEA v. Finley, No. 97-371, 1998)
One
controversy over this exception to free speech is whether obscenity
causes
real harm sufficient to justify suppression of free speech. Does
viewing
obscenity make it more likely that a man will later commit rape, or
other
acts of violence against women, obviously real harm to another person?
Does reading about war make it more likely that someone will start a
war?
Even if there is some evidence of such causal relationships, however
tenuous
or strong, is it sufficient to justify this exception to free speech?
Alternatively,
could the prohibition on obscenity be a reflection of moral values and
societal standards which should more properly be handled in the private
sector through moral education, not government censorship?
Another
problem area is determining what counts as "obscenity". In Miller,
the court tried to fashion a standard which could be adapted to
different
communities, so that what counts as obscenity in rural Mississippi
might
not count as obscenity in Atlanta or New York City. Is this fair? Do
the
people in those areas themselves agree on community standards? What is
the "community" for art that is displayed on-line on the Internet?
Another
controversy in the Miller standard is the exception for
"serious
literary, artistic, political or scientific value." Who decides what
counts
as "serious"? If some people consider Penthouse or the National
Enquirer to be serious literature, is it elitist to deny them this
exception from censorship as "obscenity"? Given the controversies in
contemporary
art (found objects, performance art, and so forth), what counts as
artistic
value? Has the Court solved the problem of defining "obscenity" or only
made it more complicated?
In reviewing these classic exceptions to free speech, it does seem that real harm can be caused by at least some of these instances of speech. Following J.S. Mill, we could limit our restrictions to real harm -- physical or economic harm, not psychic or hypothetical harm. If real harm is present, then we should next address the causal relationship necessary to hold someone responsible for the harm caused by the expression. This is not easy, of course, but we do have models for determining when a causal relationship is sufficiently close ("proximate") to hold someone responsible. We also have experience in determining whether to hold people responsible based on whether a reasonable person knew or should have known the consequences of their actions.
In addition to these established exceptions to freedom of expression, there are examples of speech which would not cause real harm, in Mill's sense, but which some believe justify suppression of speech: Offense | Establishment of Religion
(7) Offense: Although rejected by American courts, some theorists argue that speech which is merely offensive to others should be another exception to the First Amendment.(5) In a court challenge to an NEA-funded exhibit, David Wojnarowicz: Tongues of Flame, David Fordyce and Yvonne Knickerbocker claimed that the exhibit caused them to "[suffer] a spiritual injury and that the exhibition caused offense to their religious sensibilities." (Fordyce v. Frohnmayer, 763 F.Supp. 654, 656 [D.D.C. 1991]) The court rejected the claim, especially as "plaintiffs do not even allege that they have either seen the exhibition or studied the catalogue . . . [and thus] have failed to show that they have endured any special burdens that justify their standing to sue as citizens." Id. But the court left open the possibility that the plaintiffs might have a claim if "they had to confront the exhibition daily, . . . the exhibition was visible in the course of their normal routine, or . . . their usual driving or walking routes took them through or past the exhibition." Id.
The
complexities of this issue are highlighted when other examples are
considered.
What if an exhibit celebrated the practice of some religions of female
genitalia mutilation? Should such exhibits be accorded the full
protection
of the First Amendment despite the horror which most feel about such
"religious"
practices? Are there some expressions which are so extremely offensive
to many in the population that they should be banned by the government,
even though they cause no real harm to anyway? By what criteria should
this be decided?
(8) Establishment of Religion: Some speech is restricted because it constitutes the establishment of religion, which is itself prohibited by the First Amendment to the U.S. Constitution. ("Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion.") Prayer led by a principal in a public school would violate the establishment clause. Thus, a school policy prohibiting the principal from leading such prayers would not violate the right of free speech. This is controversial to some, who believe that banning prayer in the public schools limits an equally important right, freedom of religion. This tension illustrates the not-uncommon challenge of balancing competing and perhaps even irreconcilable values in the Constitution.
In challenging the Wojnarowicz exhibit, the plaintiffs (above) argued that the exhibit was critical of their Christian beliefs and thus violated the establishment clause. The plaintiffs said that they
view the public display of the exhibition as an affront to their liberty to practice religion free from governmental entanglement and politically divisive governmental intrusion into the affairs of religion. (Id. at 655)But the court said "that merely asserting spiritual injury under the establishment clause is insufficient to support standing to sue as a citizen." (Id. at 656)
Of
interest here is the difference between spiritual injury, physical
injury
or harm, and economic harm. Why are the latter two sufficient to
suppress
speech, but not the former? What criteria seem to be involved in making
such a distinction?
A future plaintiff might be able to show sufficient and direct suffering, but another consideration would rule out such challenges to NEA grants. To violate the Establishment clause, "Congress . . . [must have decided] how the . . . funds were to be spent, and the executive branch, in administering the statute, was merely carrying out Congress' scheme." (6) At NEA, in contrast, Congress does not "[participate] in the decision to grant or deny applications for federal funding, . . . . [nor does] NEA merely [administer] a congressional directive." (Id.) This means that if NEA denied a grant based on possible violation of the Establishment Clause, it might violate the free speech clause of the First Amendment.(7) Note that this reasoning seems to leave open the possibility of a grant by NEA to promote appreciation for Creationism.
D. Philosophical Consideration of Freedom of Expression
The English philosopher John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) articulated what might be called the "liberal" or (better) the "libertarian" position on freedom of expression in his 1859 book On Liberty. (8) His test for appropriate government interference with human liberties is his well-known "harm" principle, found in Chapter I:
. . . the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant. (9)
This basic principle provides an excellent rule-of-thumb for approaching issues of freedom of expression. Most of the classic exceptions to freedom of expression, as established by the U.S. Supreme Court, are consistent with this harm principle. The major exception is the legal prohibition on obscenity, to which Mill would object on the grounds that it does not cause real harm.
Mill appeals to several principles in defending his position on freedom of expression. First, how would we know which opinions to suppress as untrue? We are not, after all, infallible. Second, many opinions include at least some truth. Only through vigorous debate of conflicting opinions does the truth eventually come out. Third, even if the opinions selected by the government as true were indeed true, people would not necessarily believe it, but would consider it prejudice. Fourth, the government-approved opinions would not be understood and appreciated by the public, as the views would not have been developed "from reason or personal experience."(10)
Contemporary philosophers following Mill's approach have summarized the exceptions to freedom of expression established by the U.S. Supreme Court. Joel Feinberg, for example, has considered "how the liberal [i.e., Mill's] principles that support free expression of opinion generally also define the limits to what the law can permit to be said." (11) Carl Cohen has also used this approach in analyzing limits on freedom of expression.(12)
Critics of Mill's approach to freedom of expression generally accept the harm principle as a justification for suppressing speech, but claim that additional reasons are sufficient to suppress speech. Patrick Devlin and Edmund Pincoffs, for example, believe that the government should enforce morality and thus should legislate morality, suppressing speech to further that goal. (13) Others criticize Mill's assumption that a successful democracy depends upon freedom of expression for a healthy debate about the issues.(14)
Discussion questions
A
popular public art project in recent years has been the placement of
poetry
posters on public transportation for people to read while commuting.
Imagine
a project to place these posters in busses and subways with the content
of the Andres Serrano's "Piss Christ" that presumably would be
offensive
to some religious sensibilities. What arguments would support
exhibition
of the posters on the bus? Should a government agency provide funding
for
the poster? Why or why not?
If
a consumer reporter said falsely that a restaurant served her food with
cockroaches in it, the restaurant could maintain a lawsuit for
defamation.
If a food critic wrote a review that, in the opinion of the critic, the
restaurant's food tasted dreadful, the restaurant could not maintain a
lawsuit for defamation. Yet, if the critic is a respected food critic
in
the city, that opinion could cause as much (if not more) economic harm
to the restaurant than the erroneous news report of the consumer
reporter.
Does the distinction between "falsehood" and "opinion" result in fair
results
for the restaurant? Is the rationale for allowing defamation lawsuits
as
a restriction on speech justifiable?
NOTES
1. "A communication is defamatory if it tends to so harm the reputation of another as to lower him in the estimation of the community or to deter third persons from associating or dealing with him." American Law Institute Restatement of the Law of Torts, Second, Sec. 550. Return to text
2. This classic exception is credited to Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes: "The most stringent protection of free speech would not protect a man in falsely shouting fire in a theatre and causing a panic." (I) Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919). Return to text
3. The New York Times, June 10, 1993, p. A10. Return to text
4. Title V of the Telecommunications Act of 1996, signed into law on February 8, 1996. The Communications Decency Act (CDA) is codified at 47 U.S.C. 223(a)-(h). The act was struck down by the U.S. Supreme Court in Reno v. ACLU (June 26, 1997). Return to text
5. See, e.g., Louis B. Schwartz, "Morals Offenses and the Model Penal Code," Columbia Law Review LIII (1963), 669. Return to text
6. Id. at 657, quoting Flast v. Cohen, 392 U.S. 83, 101-06, 88 S.Ct. 1942, 1953-56, 20 L.Ed.2d 947. (1968). Return to text
7. A recent decision, Rosenberger v. University of Virginia, held that denying student fees to a student religious publication would constitute viewpoint discrimination and thus would violate the First Amendment protection of free speech. The University had argued, unsuccessfully, that providing the funds would violate the prohibition on Establishment of Religion in the First Amendment. 63 U.S.L.W. 4702 (1995). Return to text
8. J.S. Mill, On Liberty, Currin V. Shields, ed. (New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1956) [originally published 1859]. A public domain version is available on-line on the World Wide Web: http://wiretap.spies.com/ftp.items/Library/Classic/liberty.jsm. The latter version was originally published in 1909 by P.F. Collier, Harvard Classics, Volume 25. For edited excerpts from On Liberty, click here. Return to text
9. Ibid., p. 13. (Chapter I, Introductory) Return to text
10. Ibid., p. 64. (Chapter II, Of the Liberty of Thought and Discussion) Return to text
11. Joel Feinberg, "Limits to the Free Expression of Opinion," in Philosophy of Law (5th ed.), edited by Joel Feinberg and Hyman Gross (Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1995), pp. 262-281, p. 262. (original passage italicized) Return to text
12. Carl Cohen, "Free Speech and Political Extremism: How Nasty Are We Free to Be?" Law and Philosophy VII (1989), 263-79; reprinted, Philosophical Problems in the Law, edited by David M. Adams (Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing, 1992), pp. 257-65. Return to text
13. Edmund Pincoffs, "The Enforcement of Morality," from Philosophy of Law: A Brief Introduction (Belmont: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1991), pp. 131-141; Patrick Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals (Oxford University Press, 1965). Return to text
14. E.g., Wilmoore Kendall, "The Open Society and its Fallacies," American Political Science Review CIV (1960, 972-979. Return to text
Site developed and maintained by Julie
Van Camp, Professor of Philosophy,
California
State University, Long Beach
Your comments, questions, and
suggestions
are welcome: e-mail:
jvancamp@csulb.edu
1250 Bellflower Boulevard, Long Beach,
CA 90840-2408
Office Phone/Voice Mail: (562) 985-5854
Department Fax: (562) 985-7135
Copyright 1996-2005 Julie C. Van Camp
Permission is hereby given to print, download, and reproduce these materials for educational, personal, or scholarly purposes, but only if the copyright notice and this permission notice are reprinted in full with each copy. This material may not be sold or otherwise used for commercial purposes. [No copyright claimed in government documents or other public domain materials.]
Nothing in this material should be considered legal advice. If you have a legal problem, you should consult with experienced legal counsel. The views here are solely the responsibility of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the American Bar Association, California State University, or the National Endowment for the Arts.
Last updated: July 4, 2005